Clicky

/

Moral leadership in medicine: a book that deserves reading and re-reading

Koot Kotze is a medical doctor and researcher. He doesn’t tweet, but is always open discussing or engaging in conversation on medicine, ethics, education and more.

It is an unoriginal (but nonetheless accurate) observation that officially designated leaders frequently fail to lead well, or indeed lead at all. – Suzanne Shale1

It has been more than a decade since Suzanne Shale’s Moral Leadership in Medicine first saw publication, yet its relevance is undiminished. As evidenced by the opening quotation, the work aims to unpack an enduring mystery encountered within medicine by exploring how moral challenges are (or are not) confronted by healthcare managers.

The book provides a deeper understanding of the normative (that is, action-guiding) aspects of the decisions faced by those tasked with managing healthcare, and the empiric work is based on qualitative interviews conducted with 24 medical directors in the United Kingdom’s National Health Service. Shale’s subsequent analysis, from which she builds the book’s central argument and ethical framework, draws on a wide array of ethical influences, including philosophers such as Mary Urban Walker and Alasdair MacIntyre.

Through analysing and theorising the interviews in light of the modern healthcare system, Shale has developed the concept of moral leadership, which she defines as: being astute to the moral connotations of all that is involved in providing care, determining where action is needed, identifying situations where action is needed to improve or maintain the moral quality of care, and orchestrating the activity of other people to provide a morally appropriate response when one is required.1

This definition finds common ground with some conceptualisations of virtue ethics,2 particularly the notion of recognising what the right thing is to do, and then doing it. The focus on the “moral quality of care” as an outcome also overlaps with the ethicist Alasdair MacIntyre’s definition of “internal goods”, such as health and the alleviation of suffering, which are realised when practitioners exercise virtue. However, Moral Leadership in Medicine contains a more developed application of these ideas to healthcare and this deserves wider dissemination.

Propriety, a term which is not widely used, can also be understood by considering its more familiar opposite – impropriety.

Through analysing the moral narratives of medical directors, Shale distinguishes between “general practices of responsibility” and the “specific practices of propriety” through which these managers determined how to act in morally fraught situations. Propriety, a term which is not widely used, can also be understood by considering its more familiar opposite – impropriety. I have summarised the five specific proprieties identified by Shale, in the table below.

The five proprieties described in Moral Leadership in Medicine, summarised by Kotze (unpublished doctoral thesis).

Propriety Definition “First priority” to… Possible example
Fiduciary Promoting the interests of a beneficiary The patient Advocating on behalf of an individual patient, perhaps for a specific treatment or access to a service.
Bureaucratic Prioritising the needs of the organisation and in so doing, the needs of patients and professionals collectively. The “medical corporation”. In the short term this may mean the users/clients, but in the long term, this means the organization itself Transparently following the procedures set out by the organisation in order to safeguard the collective interests of all concerned.
Collegial Acting in a way which promotes cooperation based on goodwill and collegiality, rather than hierarchy Fellow professionals (the “collegium”) Persuading colleagues to adopt a protocol or treatment based on the evidence rather than by command.
Inquisitorial Investigating “misconduct, misbehaviour” and “mistakes”. This requires objectivity from the inquisitory, as well as “candour, regret and confession” where appropriate Justice and fair procedure Undertaking investigations or commissions of enquiry following adverse events and allowing all sides to be heard.
Restorative To restore moral relations after harm Moral relations Transparency in the wake of events that have caused harm. Restorative gestures such as apologies or remuneration.

 

It is to be predicted that “moral tension” would arise when these proprieties suggest conflicting courses of action. Yet this is precisely the point at which moral leaders should recognise the need for action, decide to act, and rally others to join in the required behaviours to safeguard quality of care.

Shale emphasises that while virtues are “manifestations of deep character”, the proprieties represent “customary behaviours” enacted in specific scenarios.

These proprieties resemble the virtues in medical practice (such as phronesis and trustworthiness), as suggested by Pellegrino and Thomasma.3 However, Shale emphasises that while virtues are “manifestations of deep character”, the proprieties represent “customary behaviours” enacted in specific scenarios. Indeed, she emphasises that these responses might be executed well whilst conflicting with the moral leader’s character.1

Some may regard their stocks of ethical guidance replete with the four principles or specific GMC directives, however this would miss the opportunity to understand, as Shale puts it, “the behaviours through which we express our commitment to duties, responsibilities [and] obligations”. Moral Leadership in Medicine provides a vital account of how the needs of patients and the aspirations of professionals are translated into actions beyond the bedside and should form part of any debate on the future of healthcare.

DOI: This book review was developed from an excerpt of the author’s doctoral thesis, which is currently unpublished. A lecture given by the author to the Society of Apothecaries is available here: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=5D1UuU3iScg

Featured book: Shale, S. (2011). Moral leadership in medicine: building ethical healthcare organizations. Cambridge University Press

References

1. Shale S. Moral leadership in medicine: Building ethical healthcare organizations. Cambridge University Press; 2011.
2. Hursthouse R, Glen P. Virtue Ethics [Internet]. Winter 202. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy2. 2022 [cited 2022 Dec 1]. Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/ethics-virtue/
3. Pellegrino ED, Thomasma DC. The virtues in medical practice. First. New York: Oxford University Press; 1993.

Featured photo by Andrew Papanikitas, 2022

Subscribe
Notify of
guest

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.

0 Comments
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
Previous Story

Progressing social prescribing: a recommendation for schemes involving link workers

Next Story

The art and science of effective giving

Latest from BJGP Long Read

Wherefore Art Thou?

‘Wherefore’, meaning ‘For what reason’, is one of the most fundamental questions we must ask in

0
Would love your thoughts, please comment.x
()
x
Skip to toolbar